To be published in: Astrobiology's Last Frontiers: Distribution
and Destiny of Life in the Universe, in "Origins: Genesis,
Evolution and the Biodiversity of Life ", ed. J. Seckbach
in the COLE series, Vol. 6, Kluwer Academic Publishers,
2003, Dordrecht, by invitation.
ASTROBIOLOGY'S LAST FRONTIERS:
Distribution and destiny of life
in the universe.
JULIAN CHELA-FLORES
The Abdus Salam
International Centre for Theoretical Physics
P.O.Box 586; Strada Costiera 11;
34136 Trieste, Italy and
Instituto de Estudios Avanzados,
Apartado Postal 17606 Parque Central,
Caracas 1015A, Venezuela.
1. Introduction
The four areas that define the new science
of astrobiology are the origin, evolution, distribution and destiny
of life in the universe. It is undoubtedly the fourth one which
is most likely to encourage interdisciplinary dialogue. This is
not only in relation with the more evident physically- and biologically-oriented
disciplines, but also with other not so close, but yet significant
branches of culture. Indeed, the destiny of life in the universe
will depend on the cosmological model that will eventually be
best supported by experiments in the high-energy physics domain;
it will also depend on observation of the largest red-shifts of
receding galaxies. The case of an ever-expanding universe is an
evident example of great interest to several areas of culture;
for if there would not be a reversal of the big bang expansion
(which seems to have some data in its favor), the possibility
of the phenomenon of life surviving on a large enough scale of
time seems unlikely.
On the other hand the distribution of life in the universe, in
spite of lacking solid theoretical, or observational bases, has
in its favor that it is an aspect of astrobiology that can be
probed in terms of a wide range of projects and space missions
especially dedicated to explore the question of whether or not
we are alone in the universe. In the companion paper (Chela-Flores,
2002) we have persevered with the hypothesis that was first formulated
during the commemoration of the centenary of Charles Darwin's
death (Dawkins, 1982). The points made on that occasion are relevant
in the context of this paper, since Darwin's theory of evolution
is assumed to be the only theory that can adequately account for
the phenomena that we associate with life anywhere in the universe.
In the present paper we examine the question whether evolution
of intelligent behavior is just a matter of time and preservation
of steady planetary conditions, and hence ubiquitous in the universe.
This question is motivated by the problem of understanding the
bases on which we can get significant insights into the question
of the distribution of life in the universe. Such information
would also have deep implications on the other frontier of astrobiology,
the destiny of life in the universe. In Secs. 2-4 arguments are
presented within the theory of evolution that lead us to a rationale,
within the life sciences, for testing the universality of Darwin's
theory.
2. To what extent is natural selection stronger than contingency?
2.1 NATURAL SELECTION VERSUS CONTINGENCY
For simplicity, in Sec. 4 we shall focus
on various degrees of convergence across all scientific disciplines
that are relevant to astrobiology. Features which become more,
rather than less similar through independent evolution, will be
called 'convergent'. In fact, convergence in biology is often
associated with similarity of function, as in the evolution of
wings in birds and bats. An example is provided by New World cacti
and the African spurge family, such as some euphorbs (for example,
the Euphorbia stapfii), and even some members of the Madagascar
Didieraceae (Didiera madagascariensis). These plants are
similar in appearance, being succulent, spiny, water-storing,
and adapted to desert conditions (Tudge, 1991; Nigel-Hepper, 1982).
However, they are classified in separate and distinct families,
sharing characteristics that have evolved independently in response
to similar environmental challenges, and hence this is a typical
case of convergence.
On the other hand, adaptive radiation is a second Darwinian concept
that will be necessary for understanding the examples in this
section that will argue in favor of restricted predictability
in astrobiology. In fact, adaptive radiation simply means evolution
of an animal, or plant group into a wide variety of types adapted
to specialized modes of life. In other words, adaptive radiation
signifies evolutionary diversification of a single lineage into
a variety of species with different adaptive properties. Darwin's
finches provide the classical example of adaptive radiation. Thirteen
species of Darwin's finches live in the Galapagos Islands. They
differ in the shape of their beaks.
It is remarkable how versatile their beaks can be: keratin, the
substance form which they are made, can be easily molded by evolutionary
pressures, thereby facilitating the origin of all the species
now inhabiting these islands. (Besides, there is an additional
species inhabiting Cocos Island in the Costa Rican territorial
waters in the Pacific ocean, north of the Galapagos Islands.)
We shall consider below, some less familiar examples of adaptive
radiation that will argue in favor of certain degree of predictability
in biology (and clearly in all its branches, particularly in astrobiolgy,
in view of the assumed universality of Darwinism).
Before we approach the central question of convergent evolution,
however, we should recall, firstly that so far factors influencing
the relative degree to which the Earth biota has been shaped are
still a debatable topic. According to the hypothesis of universal
Darwinism (cf., Sec. 1), life on Earth, and elsewhere, may have
been shaped mainly by:
(i) contingency, or by
(ii) the gradual action of evolution's main driving force (i.e.,
natural selection).
However, it may be possible to ascertain experimentally whether,
independent of historical contingency, natural selection is powerful
enough for organisms living in similar environments to be shaped
to similar ends. For this reason, it is important to highlight
the following three recent examples, which suggest that, to a
certain extent and in certain conditions, natural selection may
be stronger than chance:
o Sticklebacks (Gasterosteus spp.) are members of the fish
Gasterosteide Family; they are, in fact, small northern hemisphere
fishes with spines in front of their dorsal and ventral fins.
Empirical evidence has been presented (Rundle et al., 2000),
which demonstrates that natural selection plays a fundamental
role in the early stages of the evolution of new species. The
case in question concerns a striking example of convergent evolution:
sticklebacks were originally of marine origin (G. aculeatus),
but were trapped in three different lakes on the Canadian Pacific
coast (Lakes Priest, Enos and Paxton) at the end of the last ice-age,
as the glaciers retreated. In spite of the fact that the lakes
have remained isolated, the same two species have formed in all
three lakes.
Two non-interbreeding varieties have evolved in each lake; firstly,
a bulky bottom-dwelling (benthic) type and, secondly, streamlined
actively swimming individuals (limnetic), which feed in the open
water. The mating preferences of the fish were tested. It was
found that benthic mated with benthic, both from their own lake
and form the other two. In addition, it was found that limnetic
mated with limnetic. This remark demonstrates that natural selection
has been the driving force in the evolution that has taken place
in the above three Canadian lakes.
o Black European fruit flies (Drosophila subobscura) were
transported to California over twenty years ago. This event has
provided the possibility of testing the role of natural selection
in two different continental environments. Pacific coast D.
subobscura (Santa Barbara to Vancouver) were compared in wing-length
with European ones (from Southern Spain to the middle of Denmark).
After half a dozen generations were observed in similar conditions,
the increase in wing length was almost identical (4%). This is
a compelling case in favor of the key role played by natural selection
in evolution (Huey et al., 2000).
o Anole lizards from some Caribbean islands (Anolis spp.)
provide another example of evolutionary convergence. The islands
are Cuba, Hispaniola (shared by Haiti and the Dominican Republic),
Jamaica and Puerto Rico (the so called Greater Antilles). The
observed phenomenon suggests that in similar environments adaptive
radiation can overcome historical contingencies in order to produce
strikingly similar evolutionary outcomes. We could even say that
there has been replicated adaptive radiation in the various
islands.
In fact, what has been shown (Losos et al., 1998) is that
although it had been known for some time that dozens of species
thrive on these islands, some groups of lizards from different
islands living in similar environments also look similar. Genetic
analysis has shown that similar traits have evolved in distantly
related species for coping with similar environments (such as
tree-tops or ground-dwelling): anoles that live on the ground
have long, strong hindlegs, while those living at tree tops have
large toe-pads and short legs. Repeated evolution of similar groups
of species (both morphologically and ecologically) suggests that
adaptation is responsible for the predictable evolutionary responses
of the anole lizards of the Caribbean. Indeed, we can speak in
this case of evolutionary history repeating itself (Vogel, 1998).
These arguments support the following views:
(a) It is necessary to argue that within certain limits the outcome
of evolutionary processes might be rather predictable (Conway
Morris, 1998).
(b) Certain directions of evolution may carry such decisive selective
advantages as to have high probability of occurring elsewhere
[in the universe] as well (De Duve, 1995).
(c) The ubiquity of evolutionary convergence argues against the
view that biological diversity on this planet is unique to Earth
(Conway Morris, 2002).
2.2 CONSTRAINTS ON CHANCE
It is instructive to appreciate that several
constraints on chance are relevant to the question of whether
life elsewhere might follow pathways analogous to the transition
terrestrial ones. Various examples of constraints on chance have
been enumerated elsewhere (De Duve, 1995). We shall comment on
them and later we shall provide an additional example:
o Not all genes are equally significant targets for evolution.
The genes involved in significant evolutionary steps are few in
number, they are the so called regulatory genes. In these cases
mutations may deleterious and are, therefore, not fixed.
o Once a given evolutionary change has been retained by natural
selection, future changes are severely constrained; for example,
once a multicellular body plan has been introduced, future changes
are not totally random, as the viability of the organisms narrows
down the possibilities. For instance, once the body plan of mammals
has been adopted, mutations such as those that are observed in
Drosophila, which exchange major parts of their body, are
excluded. Such fruit-fly mutations are impossible in the more
advanced mammalian body plan.
o Not every genetic change retained by natural selection is equally
decisive. They may lead more to increasing biodiversity, rather
than contributing to a significant change in the course of evolution.
This may be illustrated within the Solanaceae family (Brown, 1966):
one tomato chromosome has a region between its center and end
('centromere' and 'telomere'), which consists of a row of segments
in which DNA is compacted into tight masses, largely inactive
in transcription ('chromomeres') in Petunia, in spite of being
another genus of the same family, the abundance of chromomeres
is not preserved, since larger blocks of heterochromatin are observed.
A tiny bit of heterochromatin may be superficially indistinguishable
from a eukaryotic 'chromomere'. These two genera illustrate how
quickly evolution can induce rearrangements of heterochromatin,
while preserving general chromosome structure; this mutation has
not contributed any significant change in the course of evolution.
Besides the constraints on chance mentioned in the last section,
we should recall the eternal confrontation deep in the fabric
of evolutionary theory, brought to popular attention by Jacques
Monod in his book Chance and Necessity (Monod, 1972).
Indeed, implicit in Darwin's work we have chance represented by
the randomness of mutations in the genetic patrimony, and their
necessary filtering by natural selection. However, the novel point
of view that astrobiology forces upon us accepts that randomness
is built into the fabric of the living process. Yet, contingency,
represented by the large number of possibilities for evolutionary
pathways, is limited by a series of constraints, as mentioned
before. What we feel is even more significant for astrobiology,
is to recognize that natural selection necessarily seeks solutions
for the adaptation of evolving organisms to a relatively limited
number of possible environments. We will see in cosmochemistry
(cf., Sec. 4.1) that the elements used by the macromolecules of
life are ubiquitous in the cosmos.
To sum up, the finite number of environments forces upon natural
selection a limited number of options for the evolution of organisms.
From these remarks we expect convergent evolution to occur repeatedly,
wherever life arises. It will make sense, therefore, to search
for the analogues of the attributes that we have learnt to recognize
in our own particular planet.
3. If local environments can shape how organisms change with time through natural selection, how frequent are cosmic environments favorable to life's origin?
In the original theory of Darwin the possibility
had been raised that local environments shape how organisms change
with time through natural selection. In view of the evidence presented
in Secs. 1 and 2, we assume that natural selection is the main
driving force of evolution in the universe. For these reasons
it is relevant to question whether local environments that were
favorable for the emergence of life on the early Earth, were at
all unique, occurring exclusively in our own solar system.
Alternatively, we may question, as we do in the present paper,
whether other environments fulfill conditions favorable to life's
origin, either within our solar system, or in any of the planets,
or satellites, in the multiple examples of solar systems known
at present. In addition, we suppose that on such bodies steady
conditions are preserved. By steady conditions it should be understood
that the planet where life may evolve is bound to a star that
lasts long enough: in other words, the time available for the
origin and evolution of life should be sufficient to allow life
itself to evolve before the solar system of the host planet, or
satellite, reaches the final stages of stellar evolution, such
as the red-giant and supernova phases. It is also assumed that
major collisions of large meteorites with the world supporting
life are infrequent after the solar system has passed through
its early period of formation.
In such steady conditions, the gradual action of natural selection
will be expected to be the dominant mechanism in evolution, in
view of the assumed universality of Darwinism (cf., Sec. 1). Besides,
convergence is expected to occur at various levels: in prebiotic
evolution (cf., Sec. 4.1), chemical evolution (cf., Sec. 4.7),
and finally, in biological evolution (cf., Sec. 4.4 and 4.5).
Fortunately, the existence of steady Earth-like planetary conditions
is an empirical question for which we will be able to give partial
answers in the foreseeable future; observational means will be
provided by progress in space interferometry. One possibility
for achieving this objective will be the Darwin Project (Fridlund,
2001).
4. Evolutionary convergence beyond the framework of biology
The above examples suggest that natural selection is powerful enough to shape organisms to similar ends, independent of contingency. We shall enumerate examples of general aspects of convergence at different levels of evolution: cosmic, planetary, molecular, biochemical and, once again, biological.
4.1 COSMIC CONVERGENCE
Hydrogen and helium make up almost the totality
of the chemical species of the Universe. Only 2% of matter is
of a different nature, of which approximately one half is made
by the five additional biogenic elements (C, N, O, S, P). From
organic chemistry we know that nuclear synthesis is relevant for
the generation of the elements of the Periodic Table beyond hydrogen
and helium and, eventually, for the first appearance of life in
solar systems. The elements synthesized in stellar interiors are
needed for making the organic compounds that have been observed
in the circumstellar, as well as in interstellar medium, in comets,
and other small bodies. The same biogenic elements are also needed
for the synthesis of biomolecules of life (cf., Sec. 4.7, "Convergence
in Biochemistry").
Besides, the spontaneous generation of amino acids in the interstellar
medium is suggested by general arguments based on biochemistry:
the detection of amino acids in the room-temperature residue of
an interstellar ice analogue that was ultraviolet-irradiated in
a high vacuum has yielded 16 amino acids, some of which are also
found in meteorites (Muñoz Caro et al., 2002; cf.,
also Bernstein et al., 2002).
4.2 CONVERGENCE IN THE FORMATION OF SOLAR SYSTEMS
Our solar system formed in the midst of
a dense interstellar cloud of dust and gas. This event may have
been triggered by the shock-wave of a supernova explosion. Indeed,
there is some evidence for the presence of silicon carbide (carborundum,
SiC) grains in the Murchison meteorite, where isotopic ratios
demonstrate that they are matter from a type II supernova (Hoppe
et al., 1997). In the case of our solar system this occurred
4.6 billion years before the present (Gyr BP). We may be observing
such a circumstellar disk around a young sun-like star (3 million
years, Myr, of age) in the constellation of Monoceros:
A spinning cloud around the young star is having the brightness
of its light regularly faded (it goes dim for 18 days every 48.3
days) by the interference of stellar photons and the cloud itself
(Kerr, 2002). Several earlier examples of circumstellar disks
are known, including a significantly narrow one around an 8 Myr
old star. (The narrowness suggests the presence of planets constraining
the disk.) The observation was by means of a spectrometer on board
of the Hubble Space Telescope (Schneider et al., 1999).
The matter of the original collapsing interstellar cloud that
does not coalesce into the star, collapses into a spinning circumstellar
disk, where planets are thought to be formed in a process of accretion
(some planetesimals collide and stay together, due to the gravitational
force). In addition, a variety of small bodies are formed in the
disk, prominent amongst which are comets, asteroids and meteorites.
4.3 CONVERGENT ORIGINS OF HYDROSPHERES AND ATMOSPHERES
Collisions of comets are thought to have
played a role in the formation of the hydrosphere and atmosphere
of habitable planets, such as the Earth. (This question may be
settled in the next few years by the fleet of space missions that
will interact with a variety of comets.) An alternative scenario
supposes that volatiles emerged form the planet's interior through
volcanic vents. The source of comets is the Oort cloud and Kuiper
belt. These two components of the outer solar system seem to be
common for other solar systems.
Hence we can also recognize evolutionary convergence in this cosmic
sense. But there are additional factors, which contribute to the
formation of habitable planets. We have already mentioned meteorites
in the context of the formation of solar systems. In fact, the
Murchison meteorite may even play a role in the origin of life:
According to chemical analyses, some amino acids have been found
in several meteorites: in Murchison we find basic molecules for
the origin of life such as lipids, nucleotides, and over 70 amino
acids (Cronin and Chang, 1993). Most of the amino acids are not
relevant to life on Earth and may be unique to meteorites. This
remark demonstrates that those amino acids present in the meteorite,
which also play the role of protein monomers, are indeed of extraterrestrial
origin.). In addition, chemical analysis has exposed the presence
of a variety of amino acids in the Ivuna and Orgueil meteorites
(Ehrenfreund et al., 2001). If the presence of biomolecules on
the early Earth is due in part to the bombardment of interplanetary
dust particles, or comets and meteorites, then the same phenomenon
could have taken place in any of other solar systems.
4.4 CONVERGENCE AT THE LEVEL OF INVERTEBRATES
The evolutionary biology of the Bivalvia, both at the level of zoology and paleontology, provide multiple examples of convergence and parallel evolution, a fact that makes difficult the interpretation of their evolutionary history (Harper et al., 2000). Specific examples of convergence in mollusks have been pointed out earlier in the case of the camaenid, helminthoglyptid and helcid snails (Chela-Flores, 2001).
4.5 CONVERGENCE AT THE LEVEL OF VERTEBRATES
The examples of sticklebacks and anole lizards (cf., Sec. 2) provide two additional examples of evolutionary convergence in the vertebrates. Earlier we pointed out further examples amongst the vertebrates: Passeriformes is a group of birds which is often confused with Apodiformes, but are not related to them. Since this example of swallows and swifts constitutes a classical example of evolutionary convergence, we need not repeat it here (Chela-Flores, 2001).
4.6 CONVERGENCE AT THE MOLECULAR BIOLOGY LEVEL
Convergent evolution is manifest at the
active sites of enzymes, in whole proteins, as well as in the
genome itself, as we proceed to show:
o The lipases and even by the serine proteases. They have identical
active sites (histidine, serine, aspartate form a catalytic triad).
On the other hand, their folding is completely different (Tramontano,
2002).
o The northern sea cod (Boreogadus saida, Svalbard Norway)
is an economically important marine fish of the family Gadidae.
It is found on both sides of the North Atlantic. The distantly
related order Perciformes with its suborder Percoidei, contains
the sea basses, sunfishes, perches, and, more relevant to our
interest, the notothenioid fishes from the Antarctic (Dissotichus
mawsoni, McMurdo Sound, Antarctica). In spite of their distant
relationship with cods, they have evolved the same type of antifreeze
proteins, in which there are repeats of the amino acids threonine,
alanine and proline (Chen et al., 1997.) These proteins
are active in the fish's blood and avoid freezing by preventing
the ice crystals from growing larger. The Antarctic fish protein
arose over 7 million years BP, while the Arctic cod first appeared
about 3 million years BP (both species arose in different episodes
of genetic shuffling).
o The blind cave fish Astyanax fasciatus are sensitive
to two long wavelength visual pigments. In humans the long wavelength
green and red visual pigments diverged about 30 Myr BP. The mammalian
lineage diverges form fishes about 400 Myr BP, but a recent episode
in evolution has granted fish multiple wavelength-sensitive green
and red pigments. Genetic analysis demonstrates that the red pigment
in humans and fish evolved independently from the green pigment
by a few identical amino acid substitutions (Yokoyama and Yokoyama,
1990), a clear case of evolutionary convergence at the molecular
level.
4.7 CONVERGENCE IN BIOCHEMISTRY
The universal nature of biochemistry has been discussed form the point of view of the basic building blocks (Pace, 2001). One of the main points made in that paper is that it seems likely that the basic building blocks of life anywhere will be similar to our own. Amino acids are formed readily from simple organic compounds and occur in extraterrestrial bodies such as the above example of meteorites (cf., the Murchison meteorite in the section on "Convergent origins of hydrospheres and atmospheres"). Themes that are suggested to be common to life elsewhere in the cosmos are the capture of adequate energy from physical and chemical processes to conduct the chemical transformations that are necessary for life: lithotropy, photosynthesis and chemosynthesis. Other factors that militate in favor of the universality of biochemistry are physical constraints (temperature, pressure and volume), as well as genetic constraints.
5. Discussion: Can history repeat itself?
Ever since the publication of The origin
of species, it has been argued that the possible course of
evolution may be dominated by either of the above-mentioned alternatives
[cf., Sec. 2, (i) and (ii)]. Random gene changes accumulating
over time may imply that the course of evolution is generally
unpredictable over time. But some care is needed in this assertion:
What is certainly unpredictable is the future of a given lineage.
This is due to the strong role in shaping life's evolutionary
pathways played by contingent factors, such as extinction of species
due to asteroid collisions with a given inhabited world, or other
calamities. However, such uncertainties are of lesser interest
to the larger issues that are relevant to astrobiology, namely
the inevitability of the appearance of biological features, such
as vision, locomotion, nervous systems, brains and, consequently
intelligent behavior.
We have argued that contingency does not contradict a certain
degree of predictability of the eventual biological properties
that are likely to evolve. We should underline "biological
property", as opposed to a "lineage", which is
clearly a strongly dependent on contingency. In the companion
paper we have sketched preliminary suggestions that would test
whether the early stages of evolution of intelligent behavior
are being driven mainly by natural selection at the cellular level
in the context of planetary science (Chela-Flores, 2002).
If biology experiments succeed, such as the ones that are being
planned in the near future, for instance in the context of the
Mars Express mission and its lander Beagle-2, or even further
ahead in time with missions to the Jovian moons, such successes
would undoubtedly have a significant impact in our culture, not
just in our scientific outlook. The influence of the new knowledge
gained in astrobiology will also be felt while discussing deep
philosophical questions, but also the influence will be felt in
natural theology. These questions may be discussed not just against
a background of our particular evolutionary line, which has been
followed up by life on Earth. Such questions ought to be discussed
already in terms of the many evolutionary lines that are hinted
at by present-day developments in astrobiology. In fact, the intercultural
dialogue is urgent for various reasons, which are strongly suggested
by astrobiology:
o A human-level type of intelligent behavior may be widespread
in the cosmos,
o Within the context of astrobiology it is clear that our human
descent does go back all the way to microorganisms and,
o ultimately, our origins go back to star dust.
Yet, these three items lie outside our present culture, in spite
of much current work in that direction. But it is not an easy
task to integrate our knowledge, particularly with so much specialization
in the nature of current research. Besides the general public
finds it difficult to interpret so much information which is already
available in the present age of informatics. In this work, my
main overall thesis has been that such an integration is not only
possible, but it is also timely, and indeed necessary.
Strictly speaking, a certain degree of predictability in astrobiology
is not on the same footing as predictability in either physics
(for instance, the exact time for an eclipse), or chemistry (for
example, the result of a chemical reaction).
It is relevant to keep in mind that from neuroscience other aspects
of the limited predictability of biology have been pointed out
for some time (Manger et al, 1998). In fact, the tremendous expansion
of the cetacean neocortex, while preserving the basic modular
subdivisions (analogous to small-brained mammals such as the mouse)
has led to a conjecture:
o There is a limited set of underlying mechanisms that are accessed
to building brains.
Thus in the course of evolutionary history repetition of similar
structures occurs. This also suggests that module size is evolutionary
stable across species. Indeed with Krubitzer we can even
question whether species differences are really so different (Krubitzer,
1995). In other words, in order to understand the evolution of
the cortex and how organisms increase in behavioral complexity,
it may be necessary to assume that anatomical alterations are
generated from similar mechanisms.
Further, while the future of a given lineage cannot be predicted
with certainty, the conjectured common mechanisms of cortex evolution,
give us some certainty of the types of modification that are likely
to occur in brain evolution. This aspect of brain evolution gives
us some confidence that to a certain extent evolutionary history
repeats itself in the context of the neurosciences, as in the
earlier examples form the evolution of multicellular organisms
(cf., Sec. 2). However, from what we have explained above, such
limited predictability is nevertheless the aspect of evolution
that is most relevant to astrobiology in relation to the question
of life in the solar system, as well as in the wider context of
evolution of intelligent behavior in the universe.
6. References
Bernstein, M.P., Dworkin, J.P., Sandford,
S.A., Cooper, G.W. and Allamandola, L.J. (2002) Racemic amino
acids from the ultraviolet photolysis of interstellar ice analogues.
Nature 416, 401-403.
Brown, S.W. (1966) Heterochromatin. Science
151, 417-425.
Chela-Flores, J. (2001) The New Science
of Astrobiology From Genesis of the Living Cell to Evolution of
Intelligent Behavior in the Universe. Kluwer Academic Publishers:
Dordrecht, The Netherlands, p. 161.
Chela-Flores, J. (2002) Can evolutionary
convergence be tested on Europa? ESA SP 518.
(To be published.)
Chen, L., DeVries, A.L. and Cheng, C-H.
C. (1997) Convergent evolution of antifreeze glycoproteins in
Antarctic notothenioid fish and Arctic cod. Proc. Natl. Acad.
Sci. USA 94, 3817-3822.
Conway Morris, S. (1998) The Crucible
of Creation. The Burgess Shale and the Rise of Animals, London,
Oxford University Press, p. 202.
Conway Morris, S. (2002) First Steps towards
defining galactic niches. Paper presented at the IAU Symposium
213 Bioastronomy 2002 Life Among the Stars. Summary of
Proceedings, Hamilton Island, Great Barrier Reef, Australia July
8-12, Australian Centre for Astrobiology, Sydney, p. 12.
Cronin, J. R. and Chang, S. (1993) Organic
matter in meteorites: Molecular and isotopic analyses of the Murchison
meteorite, in The chemistry of life's origins. Greenberg,
J. M., Mendoza-Gomez, C. X. and Pirronello, V. (eds.), Dordrecht:
Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 209-258.
Dawkins, R. (1983) Universal Darwinism,
in Evolution from molecules to men, Bendall, D.S. (ed.),
London, Cambridge University Press, pp. 403-425.
De Duve, C. (1995) Vital Dust. Life as
a cosmic imperative, New York, Basic Books, A Division of
HarperCollins Publishers, pp. 296-297.
Ehrenfreund, P., Glavin, D.P., Botta, O.,
Cooper, G. and Bada, J.L. (2001) Extraterrestrial amino acids
in Orgueil and Ivuna: Tracing the parent body of CI type carbonaceous
chondrites. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA, 98, 2138-2141.
Fridlund, M. (2001) The Darwin Mission and
Exo-/Astrobiology. ESA SP 496, 267-271.
Harper, E.M. Taylor, J.D. and Crame, J.A.
(2000) The evolutionary biology of the Bivalvia, Geological
Society Special Publication 177, London. www.palaeo-electronica.org/2001_2/books/evo.pdf
Hoppe, P., Strebel, R., Eberhadt, P., Amari,
S. and Lewis, R.S. (1997) Type II supernova matter in a silicon
carbide grain from the Murchison meteorite. Science 272,
1314-1317.
Huey, R., Gilchrist, G., Carlson, M., Berrigan,
D. and Serra, L. (2000) Rapid evolution of a geographic cline
in size in an introduced fly. Science 287, 308-309.
Kerr, R. A. (2002) Winking star unveils
planetary birthplace. Science 296, 2312-2313.
Krubitzer, L. (1995) The organization of
neocortex in mammals: are species differences so different? Trends
in Neurosci., 18, 408-417.
Losos, J. B., Jackman, T.R., Larson, A.,
de Queiroz, K. and Rodriguez-Schettino, L. (1998) Contingency
and determinism in replicated adaptive radiations of island lizards.
Science 279, 2115-2118.
Manger, P., Sum, M., Szymanski, M., Ridgway,
S. and Krubitzer, L. (1998) Modular subdivisions of dolphin insular
cortex: Does evolutionary history repeats itself? J. Cognitive
Neurosci., 10, 153-166.
Monod, J. (1972) Chance and Necessity
An Essay on the Natural Philosophy of Modern Biology, Collins,
London, p. 136.
Muñoz Caro, G.M. , Meierhenrich,
U.J. , Schutte, W.A., Barbier, B., Arcones Segovia, A., Rosenbauer,
H., Thiemann, W.H.P., Brack, A., Greenberg, J.M. (2002) Amino
acids from ultraviolet irradiation of interstellar ice analogues.
Nature 416, 403-406.
Nigel-Hepper, F. (1982) Kew: Gardens
for Science and Pleasure, London, Her Majesty's Stationary
Office, p. 81.
Pace, N. R. (2001) The universal nature
of biochemistry. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 98, 805-808.
Rundle H. D., Nagel, L., Wernick Boughman,
J. and Schluter, D. 2000, Natural selection and parallel speciation
insympatric sticklebacks. Science 287, 306-308.
Schneider, G., Smith, B. A., Becklin, E.
E., Koerner, D. W., Meier, R., Hines, D. C., Lawrence, P. J.,
Terrile, R.J., Thomson, R. I. and Rieke, M. 1999, NICMOS Imaging
of the HR 4796A Circumstellar Disk. Ap. J. 513, L1217-L130.
Tramontano, A. (2002) Private communication.
Tudge, C. (1991) Global Ecology,
London: Natural History Museum Publications. p. 67.
Vogel, G. (1998) For island lizards, history
repeats itself. Science, 279, 2043.
Yokoyama, R., and Yokoyama, S. (1990) Convergent evolution of the red- and green-like visual pigment genes in fish, Astynax fasciatus, and human. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA, 87, 9315-9318.